Wednesday, October 16, 2013

Pulling a Swift One: Confusing Philosophy with Science.

English 2107

13 July 2009
Pulling a Swift One:
Confusing Philosophy with Science.

            Swift’s satire of science so little resembles a satire of science that it’s actually very difficult to understand it as a satire of science at this far a date removed from it. It reads off like a straight attack on Pythagorean philosophy, one that could have been written at just about any point up to the year 1800. It is only through studying Swift’s life that it becomes clear that when it seems blatantly obvious that he is attacking philosophy, he is really attacking what he has confused with philosophy, namely science. Furthermore, it is only through studying a vague “meta-history” of European culture that Swift’s view that science and philosophy are interchangeable and therefore equally evil can be fully understood within it’s proper context.

             Labelling periods of history is both ambiguous and arbitrary, but it’s also often convenient when attempting to compare events that appear to occur in cycles. European history could be arbitrarily broken down into the following five periods, a violent or non-violent revolution occurring between each and with each change being the result of the import of new ideas. The first period could be dubbed the Homeric period and would comprise of the period between the third Indo-European invasion of Europe, as described by Marija Gimbutas, and the rise of philosophy on the Ionian coast. This period is not relevant to this essay, nor is the fifth and current post-WWII era of technology. The three time periods that are to be discussed are the Pythagorean or Platonic period (c. Pythagoras-Justinian, often referred to as “Antiquity”), the Christian Period (c. Justinian – Bacon, often referred to as “Medieval”) and the Scientific Period (c. Bacon – Heisenberg, which combines the Renaissance, Enlightenment and Romantic periods into one period).

The Pythagorean period is characterized by the viewpoints of Pythagoras and Parmenides, the writings of Plato and the mathematics of Archimedes and Euclid. It was a time when deductive thought was assumed to be the ideal and correct means of understanding the natural world. While Democritus may have correctly deduced an atomic theory, and Anaximander may have correctly deduced a rough theory of evolution (without natural selection and with undoubted influence from Chaldean mermen), these deductions followed from nothing but arbitrary axioms and were certainly not conclusions stemming from the results of experiments that were repeatedly demonstrated to be repeatedly demonstrable. Consequently, the leading philosophers of the day routinely discarded superior theories – such as the heliocentric system or the fact that the earth is roughly spherical – over inferior theories because they preferred the axioms that led to the inferior theories over the ones that led to the superior theories. Nonetheless, there is a rough continuity of thought between the Pythagoreans and the Scientists in the sense that they agree that the search for answers is through studying natural explanations to observable phenomena. It is therefore understandable how a Christian living in the beginning of the scientific era may have confused the new system of Science with the old system of Philosophy and managed to attack science by characterizing it as no different than the old and discredited system of philosophy.

Christianity, of course, has little in common with either Science or Pythagorean philosophy in regards to it’s methodology, despite Christianity’s clear cultural inheritance of Platonist ethics and symbolism. Christianity is based neither on inductive experiment nor on deductive thought but on an argument from authority, the authority being the scriptures. Where philosophy and science both attempt to construct consistent systems of thought based on either axioms or experiments, i.e. systems without logical paradoxes or contradictions, Christianity makes no attempt to be consistent whatsoever, as such an attempt would necessarily require a suspension of scriptural authority. In truth, Christianity even goes so far as to assume a set of logical contradictions – singular is identical to plural, life is equivalent to death, etc – and then attempt to draw deductions from these contradictions. This is not the place to criticize Christianity’s entirely conscious deficiencies of rigour; the point is that the epistemological approaches of philosophy and religion are and always have been wholly incompatible with each other, regardless of whether or not the dominant view amongst the philosophers of the era was inductive or deductive. An anonymous and now unknown Platonist of late antiquity may have even gone so far as to define philosophy and religion as cosmic opposites of each other.

So, then we have Jonathan Swift. Born in the midst of an intellectual upheaval, and yet rooted in the theories of the past. The time he spent studying for his doctorate in theology, in a time where doctor and theologian in the same phrase did not create an oxymoron, would have been more than enough time for him to stumble across entire books full of information about that strange old nemesis to Christianity, those heathens and heretics, the ones that Justinian had to shut down by force, the ones that wrote lengthy discourses on how frivolous Christianity really is[1]. What theology student wouldn’t find that fascinating? Yet, the histories obtainable to Swift would have read off like cartoons, with superhero bishops and evil villains running the academies[2]. Now, a scientist may have questioned these writings more rigorously, but Swift was not a scientist, he was a deeply religious man who was taught to take information on authority. To Swift, science was evil because it was pagan, it represented an uprising of the forces that Christianity had spent it’s entire existence fighting against, which he knew was true because he was told it was true.

Satire is primarily a subconscious stress-relieving response to the fear of a deep fear being actualized in front of you (Zoglin). Hence, satirists tend to go after targets that they feel threatened by – political leaders or ideas, systems of thought, business competitors. Swift may have been deeply conservative, but he wasn’t completely disconnected from his time, he saw what he would have declared as “the rise of paganism” tearing down the ancient barriers, and this would have deeply frightened him. Imagine! Heathens! Heretics! All around us! They will undo the Christian religion and all of England, under the tyranny of the so-called Philosopher Kings, will be bound by chains and worshipping Apollo in the churches in no time!

See, fear is also often irrational. It’s often based on confusion; certainly, Newton wasn’t going around sacrificing mead, even though he was denying the trinity[3], and even though some of the Masonic organizations around at the time actually were doing more esoteric things along those lines.

And, see, this is how ignorance spreads: paranoia fuses all of one’s enemies together into one evil monster, it combines Masonic rituals, experimental methodology, Pythagorean philosophy and it’s superstitious dark age offshoots – such as alchemy, physiognomy and astrology – and the growing rationalist opposition to Christianity into one evil of nearly unthinkable proportions: Science.

The first thing to note is that Swift’s conception of England was of a modern, protestant, business-oriented society – far superior to the pseudo-pagans on the south of the continent. Swift also articulates his disdain for the uncivilized Dutch, whom he accuses of being less merciful than “heathens” (Swift 148). Ridiculing an individual of Dutch ancestry by questioning his religious devotion and then comparing him negatively to “heathens” certainly seems rather unsophisticated at this date, but the juvenility of the discourse was reasonable within the context of the mindset of the era, considering that Dutch and British shipping interests were in the midst of a long struggle. These targeted comments, which appear in the first chapter of the third part of Swift’s text, haphazardly demonstrate the profound racial, religious, linguistic and ethnic xenophobia that characterized the society that Swift existed within and consequently shaped his thoughts and views.

By claiming that the islanders speak an unknown romance language, he immediately sets the reader up to compare the society on the island to one under Roman Catholic rule, which, at the time, could only be a reference to the papacy as the Roman Emperor, King of France and King of Spain were all Germans. However, given the way the story unfolds, it seems more likely that Swift really misspoke here. While Swift knew that most of the arguments he had read about while studying theology were directed at the Romans, particularly the eastern Romans, he did not know that by the time an antagonistic discourse had developed between Christianity and Pythagoreanism, the Roman Empire had adopted the Greek language and taken on a fundamentally Greek identity. Swift appears to have incorrectly thought that Porphyry and Plotinus both wrote in Latin.

If Swift is really consciously satirizing the Pythagoreans, the island could very well be representative of Atlantis, or, more accurately, Francis Bacons’ New Atlantis. Atlantis, the archetypal utopian society, was first described by Plato and was used as the model of utopia throughout the Pythagorean era. Bacon wrote a text entitled “The New Atlantis” that was essentially a plan to construct a workable version of Plato’s ideal society. Laputa, Atlantis and the new Atlantis all share the characteristics of being highly isolated and highly technological societies. Swift’s tract could very well be seen as an attempt to discredit Bacon’s ideas by tying them to evil pagan religion.

Swift’s satire is so heavy-handed that a collection of simple quotes is sufficient to demonstrate his views. Swift makes his intentions clear near the start of the second chapter, when he clearly describes the Laputians in Pythagorean terms. The Laputians, like the Pythagoreans, are obsessed with astronomy and music. Swift even satirizes the Pythagorean oath of silence:
Their outward Garments were adorned with the Figures of Suns, Moons, and Stars, interwoven with those of Fiddles, Flutes, Harps, Trumpets, Guittars, Harpsichords, and many more Instruments of Musick, unknown to us in Europe … It seems the Minds of these People are so taken up with intense Speculations, that they neither can speak, nor attend to the Discourses of others. (Swift 152)

Next, Swift satirizes the philosopher king:    
At last we entered the Palace, and proceeded into the Chamber of Presence; where I saw the King seated on his Throne, attended on each Side by Persons of prime Quality. Before the Throne, was a large Table filled with Globes and Spheres, and Mathematical Instruments of all Kinds. His Majesty took not the least Notice of us, although our Entrance were not without sufficient Noise, by the Concourse of all Persons belonging to the Court. But he was then deep in a Problem, and we attended at least an Hour, before he could solve it. (Swift 155)

Now, swift satirizes ideal forms:
In the first Course, there was a Shoulder of Mutton, cut into an A Equilateral Triangle; a Piece of Beef into a Rhomboides; and a Pudding into a Cycloid. The second Course was two Ducks, trussed up into the Form of Fiddles; Sausages and Puddings resembling Flutes and Haut-boys, and a Breast of Veal in the Shape of a Harp. The Servants cut our Bread into Cones, Cylinders, Parallelograms, and several other Mathematical Figures. (Swift 155-156)

            Now that it is blatantly clear that the victim of Swift’s tirades is not science but Platonist philosophy, it is interesting to point out that Swift even goes so far as to regurgitate the views of Plato’s largest critic, his pupil Aristotle, as can be found in the Metaphysics: 
On the other Side, after having seen all the Curiosities of the Island, I was very desirous to leave it, being heartily weary of those People. They were indeed excellent in two Sciences for which I have great Esteem, and wherein I am not unversed; but at the same time so abstracted and involved in Speculation, that I never met with such disagreeable Companions. I conversed only with Women, Tradesmen, Flappers, and Court-Pages, during two Months of my Abode there, by which at last I rendered my self extremely contemptible; yet these were the only People from whom I could ever receive a reasonable Answer. (Swift 169)
            It is here that we come to the real heart of Swift’s views on philosophy. There is truly little independent thought in what he has written; he is merely regurgitating the established Christian and Aristotelian attacks against Pythagoreanism, which he is unable to distinguish from Baconian science. Swift is clearly widely read; had he taken the time to disentangle Pythagoreanism from science, he may have come to entirely different conclusions. However, he didn’t take the time to disentangle the new system from the old system that it resembled so shallowly and, as such, should be regarded as merely another ignorant voice at the end of an era of ignorance.






Works Cited
1)      Swift, Jonathan. “A voyage to Laputa, Balnibarbi, Luggnagg, Glubbdubdrib and
Japan.” Gulliver’s Travels. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977. 147-180.
2)      Porphyry. Against The Christians.  Lost text. c. 300.
3)      Tertullian. “De Spectaculis”. Apology. De Spectaculis.. London: Heinemann, 1931.
Internet Archive. Jul. 12 2009.
<http://www.archive.org/stream/apologydespectac00tertuoft>
4)      Zoglin, Richard. “Harry Shearer on Political Satire.” Time Magazine. 18 Jul. 2008  Time Inc.. Jul. 12 2009. <http://www.time.com/time/arts/article/0,8599,1824482,00.html>
5)      Newton, Isaac. An Historical Account of Two Notable Corruptions of Scripture. London: John Green, 1841. Google Books. 12 Jul. 2009 <http://books.google.co.uk/books?id=cIoPAAAAQAAJ&pg=PA1>










Works Not Cited
1)      Gimbutas, Marija. The Kurgan Culture and the Indo-Europeanization of Europe. Washington: Institute for the Study of Man, 1997.
2)      Berryman, Sylvia. “Democritus.” The Stanford Encyclopedia Of Philosophy. Aug. 15, 2004. Stanford University, Center for the Study of Language and Information. 12 Jul. 2009. <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/democritus/>
3)      Couprie, Dirk. “Anaximander.” The Internet Encylopedia of Philosophy. 2006. 12 Jul. 2009. <http://www.iep.utm.edu/a/anaximan.htm >
4)      Stevenson, David. The Origins of Free Masonry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
5)      “Anglo-Dutch Wars”, Wikipedia, 10 Jul. 2009. Wikimedia Foundation, Inc.. 12 Jul. 2009 <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Anglo-Dutch_Wars>
6)      Aristotle. Metaphysics. Tran: W.D. Ross. Internet Classics Archive. 12 Jul. 2009 <http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html>


[1] Porphyry, Against the Christians, c 300.
[2] Tertullian, “De Spectaculis”, Apology. De Spectaculis. (London: Heinemann, 1931), 230-304.
[3] Newton, Isaac, An Historical Account of Two Notable Corruptions of Scripture (London: John Green, 1841) , 1-88.

http://dghjdfsghkrdghdgja.appspot.com/thoughts/essays/swift.html